"A friendly, informal discussion group."

The Yale Student Roundtable hosts weekly discussions over pizza where we try to expand our understanding of a variety of issues. Sometimes two hours isn't enough to get to the bottom of an issue, so this blog is an opportunity to remind yourself of the major points of our discussions and add your comments.

Saturday, January 31, 2009

Should minorities be allowed to make their own laws?

0 responses

--What are the limits of tolerance in liberal societies? --What amounts to signing a social contract?--When can community self-determination supersede individual rights claims?

Are the identities and cultures of minority groups valuable? "Yes," said the roundtable, affirming a sentiment perhaps difficult to disagree with. But should religious and tribal groups be allowed to sacrifice their goats, marry their cousins, or engage in cannibalism within the borders of the US? "Uhh...No," said the group.

For such cases, it was relatively to judge that a national government's duty to prevent egregious violations of human and animal well-being would trump cultural claims to their legitimacy. Yet beyond extreme examples, the group considered whether more efforts should be made to legally accommodate the cultural practices of minority groups. Roundtablers agreed that a good deal of value lay in allowing minority groups defined by some sort of cultural ties to preserve their customs and traditions. Since such represented a general "right" of these peoples to preserve these groups identity, free expression, and beliefs, a regard for such groups' "cultural rights" ideally should be represented with regards to the law.

How could such efforts be made? Should different laws apply to different segments of the populace… so as to accommodate those of different beliefs? One roundtabler noted that such a policy was adopted in India. For instance, turban-wearing Sikhs were allowed to carry daggers on their person while others were forbidden to. Perhaps such a policy was necessary to satisfy members of different religions. Yet the same roundtabler also pointed out that the policy could also deepen group divisions in a country by reinforcing differences.

Another discussant proposed that regional cultural differences could best be accommodated by increasing powers of local legislation. The national government would outline basic protections and guidelines, then allow local communities to decide the details of more specific cultural issues. Yet others noted the both logistical difficulties and fundamental problems with this concept. Someone asserted that certain issues, such as gay marriage or others pertaining to the rights of individuals, illustrated the case for uniform policies across the nation. Would it make sense for a couple be legally married in one state but fail to have that status, and the rights such represents, recognized in another? Additionally, dividing sovereignty from locale to locale could cause confusion when people desired to travel across borders and a feeling of disconnect between them akin to the creation of many different “nations” within the whole as geographical group divisions were reinforced.

Other roundtables yet considered the mechanisms of inclusion already existent in our democratic pluralist system. To a large extent, perhaps our status as a “melting pot” nation, long accustomed to many diverse groups, already makes us lean towards efforts of general inclusion; a roundtabler noted one example of multilingual election materials. Additionally, unlike France, the US only bans extreme public expression of religion such as preaching in schools. Perhaps for the needs of most religious and ethnic groups, American democratic politics is perhaps inclusive enough to accommodate a sufficient amount of uniqueness and variation.

Yet perhaps the cases of certain groups required different consideration, specifically those of indigenous groups such as the Aborigines or the Native Americans. The Roundtable noted that these groups might both require and merit more legal leeway than the regular political system could provide. For these groups, the need for greater autonomy was more clearly necessary for their needs of self-preservation since their cultures were so greatly divergent from the national mainstream; having their lifestyles governed by laws of the national norm would be too much of a threat to their cultural identities. These groups could have a compelling case for greater sovereignty within their territories since these groups had long desired to exist like separate nations even since the founding of the Australian and American states, respectively. Perhaps our right to intervene in such groups’ practices should be extremely limited since participation in their culture is a voluntary choice.

Perhaps the Roundtable thus stayed true to its American bias, firmly believing in the value of our “melting-pot”-“patchwork-quilt”-call-it-what-you-may nation to hash out its internal differences through a(n at least relatively) inclusive national political process. “Unity in diversity,” we say, except for Charlie’s Aborigines.

Saturday, January 24, 2009

Should parents deceive their children about the existence of Santa Claus?

2 responses

--Should parents ever lie to their children? --Is it healthy to encourage unrealistic expectations (like the notion of a prince charming)? --When should we choose happiness over truth? --Does Santa Clause actually exist?

"Ho ho ho" or "Bah humbug?" It was up to the Roundtable to decide in a session where, perhaps unsurprisingly, a discussion on society's relationship to Kris Kringle and other tales evolved into debates regarding the relative values of truth and ideals, the role and power of myth in society, and the acceptability of certain "noble lies," among other things.


We began with a discussion of the stories told to children. Were tales of Santa Claus, the Tooth Fairy, fairy tales, and the like only little white lies told for the purpose of entertainment and enchantment? Were they just obvious mistruths, presented to those not yet old enough to know better or comprehend the world in its full complexity? (One would hope that ) all of us in the Roundtable agreed that gifts encountered in years past under Christmas trees or pillows were not in fact delivered by Santa, the Tooth Fairy, Hannukah Harry, or the Holiday Armadillo. Thus a belief in these figures' existence, and the elaborately-crafted stories around such, would be factually incorrect. But was the Kris Kringle question simply one of truth versus falsehood?


The roundtable thus could not help but to ponder for a while the nature of "truth," reality, and myth. Roundtablers considered viewing the stories of Santa Claus much like modern myths due to the elaborate stories surrounding the figure, the cultural and religious origins of the stories and traditions, and their deep and widespread presence in our culture. Along this vein, a roundtabler noted that the concept of myth versus truth perhaps was not simply one to be evaluated with logic alone; another noted that in many ways even adult American culture and society is still in many ways full of myth. In matters like the representation of national history and tradition, perhaps what is "true" could still remain somewhat ambiguous even in adult society; differing values could lead to differently-slanted stories of how things came to be. An example was the portrayal of great historical figures such from George Washington to Martin Luther King, Jr; over time perhaps the stories we have heard of their accomplishments and virtues have mythologized them in our consciousness, such that we could overlook certain less-convenient realities about them, such as alleged extramarital affairs of the latter.


This example shed some more light on the meaning of our Santa Claus storytelling. Perhaps even tales that we could easily identify as fantasy actually sought to convey another meaning beyond factual representation of events. After all, stories of Santa Claus in fact originated from Christian traditions and the underlying messages of rewards for good behavior and a benevolent judge of actions communicate clear moral values. While mythical stories that channel this spirit may be entirely fabricated, a roundtabler suggested that essence speaks to a sort of "human truth" comprised of morals, perhaps even a universal one along the lines of Carl Jung's considerations. More than serving as simply entertaining lies, certain childhood stories might serve as channels for the moral and cultural education of the young generation and reflect very much our own adult society's tendency to mythologize.


While telling childhood myths may have great power, the roundtable found it important to consider what was gained and lost through this practice. Should the possible instructive and cultural value of these stories be weighed against the aspect of distortion and deception that they entail? While childhood stories may seem to be an apt way to either teach lessons or explain complex ideas in an easily-digestible form, do parents really need to lie to their children in order to accomplish these goals? Would children be better off without these stories? The group agreed that an individual for whom credence in Claus remained unchallenged would certainly be ill-served. Yet for most of us our discovery of the "real world" seemed to inevitably occur in time as we (again, hopefully) matured. The group as a whole thus could not agree as to where to draw the line between the sacredness of Santa and any possible alternatives. Who knew Claus was so controversial?

Saturday, January 17, 2009

What makes a war just?

2 responses

--Is it ever just for a country to engage in a war in which it is the aggressor? --What rights should enemy civilians lose? --Are the people of a democracy responsible for the war of their government?

The first YSR discussion of the semester began with a rather explosive topic: war. In attempting to determine what legitimizes a war’s initiation, what rules and standards apply to war once under way, and the responsibilities of individual citizens in war situations, the group inevitably struggled to define the very concept of justice in various situations of human interaction.

Discussion began with attempts to put forth a definition of justice for the basis of our consideration. Nick was the first to suggest that justice is most simply what is “owed to someone” in a given situation, and the group subsequently referred to this definition a good deal as the discussion progressed. Yet other considerations arose. Was justice about utilitarianism or morality, retribution or mercy? Did justice stem naturally from rather universal conceptions of human good or was it more like a societal construct called upon to preserve order or rationalize certain actions?

Justice in the abstract proved difficult to pin down, but Elah introduced a hypothetical framework for considering justice of inter-state conflict, with her example of two groups facing a dilemma over limited water resources in the desert. In such a situation in which the interests of one group meant harm towards another, how should or could the justice of each group’s actions be judged? Nate B, the resident economist, proposed that cost-benefit considerations of maximizing total lives be the best measure of objective justice, yet Joe C argued that the ability to consider and plan such situations with a sense of “God-in-the-sky” omniscient objectivity was not always possible in real life.

Extending the survival-in-the-desert example to real state warfare, Phil advocated that in such “desert” cases, war launched by a state would be just if it were “necessary” to address a threat to its survival. Others, though, noted that such a definition could leave room for ambiguity in determining justice due to the imperfect way in which states dealt with uncertainty in calculating the appropriate responses to threats. Could it ever be possible to objectively calculate the absolute justice of a state’s actions, much less the relative justice of one group’s interests over another in a “well-in-the-desert” situation?

In addition to considering the justice of wars, the group also discussed justice in conduct of wars. When considering war as affecting people on an individual scale, members of the roundtable invoked more concerns of justice as human mercy and morality. Ben asked us to consider the permissibility of killing a Frenchman in wartime versus in peacetime, and Danie posed the question of whether war meant a suspension of person-to-person justice in favor of different rules of justice between nations.

Are these justices distinct from one another, in our minds, and in the real world? We considered such in discussing where the individual fit in as a citizen during wartime. How much was the individual citizen responsible for the actions of his/her government? How much ought a citizen stand by one’s nation or have a duty to protest aspects of a war s/he found unjust? Perhaps as both a member of a national group and an individual human being, the individual citizen finds him/herself somewhat caught between the impersonal justice of necessity between nations and notions of justice linked to human “morality” (whose definition seems to demand more YSR discussions to ever agree upon). These considerations seemed to all lead us back to the group’s earlier definitions of justice. Members suggested that such a definition of what one “owes someone” seemed to speak of justice as applying values to different people, interests, groups, and causes when calculating what is appropriately “owed.” Matt suggested that such could be the flaw inherent in any one group attempting to judge justice. Perhaps this is the reason that the search for a perfectly objective measure of world war justice remains elusive and that the Security Council always seems unable to agree with itself. Maybe we might as well have YSR take over the world and be the judge.